Review of
Jean-Louis Harouel:
la grande falsification:l'art contemporain
éditions jean-cyrille godefroy (2009)
In France, the protest against what is called 'l'art
contemporain' is growing steadily. Already in 1983, Jean Clair published
his 'Considérations sur l'état des beaux-arts'
(1983), soon followed by contributions of Jean-Philippe Domecq in
Esprit in the early nineties. But it is Jean
Baudrillard who belled the cat with his 'Le
complot de l'art.' in Libération' (1996). The debate is fought not
only in journals and magazines, but also in a meanwhile impressive
series of books: 'Artistes sans art? (1994)
and 'Misère de l'art' (1999)
by Jean-Philippe Domecq, 'Les mirages de l'art contemporain' (2005) by
Christine Sougrins, 'La querelle de l'art
contemporain' (2005) van
Marc Jimenez, 'Pour l'art' (2006) by Kostas Mavrakis, 'L'art caché' (2007)
by
Aude de Kerros , 'Ou est passé l'art?' by
Christian Delacampagne, 'Malaise dans les musées' (2007) by Jean Clair, 'Paris-New York et retour'
(2009) by
Marc Fumaroli'. The unease with 'l'art contemporain' is found among a
broad array of intellectuals, including old leftists of different
feathers - just think, next to Baudrillard and Kostas Mavrakis, of
figures like
Jacques Rancière, who describes 'relational aesthetics' as a 'nebula that
contends that art is not an object but produces social relations'. The
last important intervention in this 'querelle de
l'art contemporain' is 'La grande falsification; L'art contemporain'
(2009) by Jean-Louis Harouel. Let us have a closer look at this
contribution.
SUMMARY
In his introduction, Harouel declares that art has become 'anti art,
non art, a hoax', 'an imposture, a joke, a mystification',
'anything, but art' (p 7). He quotes Duchamp himself: 'One can make people
swallow anything'.
In the first chapter, Harouel contends that the crisis of art was inaugurated by the invention of photography. The
painters lost their monopoly 'on the reproduction of the real' (p.14).
From 1850 onward, an economic war is waged between painters and
photographs.
Some painters explore new ways of painting that remain inaccessible to
photographers, and degrade the painters who continue to follow the
trodden
paths as
'pompiers'. Artists have always been looking for improvements, but only
in view of 'realising an even better reproduction of the real' (p. 33)
From 1850 onward the quest is rather for a 'less good figuration' (p.
34). Malevich' 'white square on a white background' and Duchamp's urinal
are the endpoint of this quest: the end of art. In an 'effort to selvage
the prestige of the painter, the painters try to
'distinguish themselves at all costs by some lucky find' (p. 34). After
the end of art, the cult of the 'artists without art' is inaugurated' (Domecq).
The justification of this development is provided by German Idealism
(Novalis, Schlegel, Hölderlin, Schelling), as well as by underlying
movements like Neo-Platonism, Gnosis, Jakob Böhme, Swedenborg, Schopenhauer,
theosophy, anthroposophy and Rosicrucian's (p.48). This leads
to the idea of an artist as someone who has access to a hidden reality, who
stays in
direct contact with the divine or the cosmos, who is able to transform
the world, who exerts magical powers (p.
45). That explains the reciprocal sympathy between the millenarian
expectations of art and revolutionary political movements (p. 66). Harouel
reminds of the fact that belief in invisible worlds can go hand in hand
with realistic rendering (p. 64) and describes in detail how 'the
predilection of spiritualism for bad rendering' comes about (p.67).
In the third chapter, Harouel has a closer look at the phenomenon of the
'artist without art''
(Philippe Domecq):
the replacement of the cult of art with the cult of the artist as a
priest, a prophet, a shaman, a philosopher (p. 100). The question
is no longer to make good art - anything will do - but to have oneself
recognised as an avant-garde artist (p. 93). The artist stands above law
and morality. He can best be
described as a swindler, who is allowed to do as he likes under the
cover of art.
In a last chapter, Harouel describes how 'l'art contemporain' could obtain
such a dominant position. Until the Second World War, modern art
enjoyed the necessary attention, but could not win the sympathy of
the masses in the big democracies. Things change as soon as Stalin and
Hitler come to reject modern art. Under Peggy Guggenheim's motto - 'When
the Nazis reject it, it must be good'' (p. 152) - Nelson Rockefeller (MoMA)
proclaims modern art as the symbol of the Free World in 1949, and Richard Barr (MoMA)
uses it as a weapon against communism
(Pollock in Life Magazine). This movement is endorsed by the CIA.
Rockefeller becomes the model for other wealthy people.
Harouel does not blame them for being successful entrepreneurs, but for
lacking the necessary culture. The same goes for many a politician. 'An
art that is none' fits them like a glove. They become the models for
figures like François Pinault and
Bernard Arnault in France. To stress the continuity with the past, they
organise 'dialogues' where non-art is put at the same level as real art.
ANYTHING?
To begin with, let us remark that Harouel uses a rather narrow
definition of art: the image must be 'recognisable as well as
transfigured by the artist' (p 128). The emphasis is on the
'recognisable': already the reduction of space with Manet and the use of
'unnatural colours' by Gauguin are problematic for Harouel. He thus
excludes not only many acknowledged artist - think of Greco, but also of
pre-Renaissance and non-European art but also many valuable works
that could only be created by abandoning 'literal rendering' -
just think of Paul Klee, who is not even mentioned by Harouel.
Equally to narrow is the claim that the image has to result from the
cooperation of hand and eye. Already in finger painting, the material is
playing an important role. In more advanced handicraft techniques,
next to materials, also the instruments play a constitutive role
(pencil, brush, burin)
(think of 'Eloge de la main', Focillon, 1934). In techniques such as
mosaic or prints, the share of materials, instruments and support
only increases. In photography, even more aspects of the production are
mechanised, but countless interventions are performed manually, and
there is a close cooperation between the eye that looks through the
lens, and the hands that holds the camera or the body: think of the
ballet performed by the photographer before his subject. Hence, one
cannot exclude techniques like photography - not to mention
techniques that are not mentioned, like the collage, the
mimetic object (think of
Picasso's bull), and 'lower' genres like comic, cartoon,
graffiti and what have you. Moreover, it suffices to refer to poetry and the
novel to realise that cooperation of hand and eye -, or more generally: a
definition in terms of technical genre - cannot be invoked to decide
whether something is art or not.
We need a more encompassing definition of mimesis, one that allows not
only for the rendering of imaginary worlds (completed mimesis),
but also for a broad array of techniques, as well as of ways of
rendering (many kinds of mimetic media). Only then do we no longer have to exclude Japanese prints, pre-Renaissance art and many
forms of modern art. On the basis of such a broader definition, we can
determine precisely where the real boundaries of art are crossed: where
art is transformed into design (already since Brancusi, Tatlin, Lissitzky
and Mondrian), where it proceeds to display reality
(already since the urinal of Duchamp, and again with Pierre Restany and
Arte Povera), where it proceeds to the use of non-verbal language for a
philosophical discourse or for symbolic actions (performance, Aktionen, conceptual
art, 'relational art, and what have you.
His narrow definition prevents Harouel from realising that, beyond its
boundaries, art does not degenerate into 'anything' - does not disappear in
the black hole of 'non art'. Only a proper definition shows that art is a
domain that is surrounded by design and displayed reality.
From a negative point of view, crossing the borders comes down to a
disqualification as art, but, from a positive point of view, it amounts
to entering a new domain of human creativity. The pedestals of Brancusi,
the designs of
Tatlin, the Proun spaces of Lissitzky,
the 'Salon de Madame B' of Mondrian, many creations of Gabo, Pevsner,
Donald Judd , Carl
André and Anish Kapoor, cannot be called sculptures - artworks - but they
are magnificent creations nevertheless. And, although the works of Duchamp,
Manzoni, Beuys, Wim Delvoye
or Demand can by no means called art, we are dealing with sometimes very
interesting forms of non-verbal discourses, with pertinent symbolic
actions, or with interesting examples of art theories (from Duchamp to Demand). One can only object the fact that
they are posing for art, rather than inscribing themselves in the
traditions where they really belong, and where they can be judged on
their own merits (see for instance Jan de Cock).
Rather than fulminating against the 'anything' or 'le non-art', it
matters to call things by name: art, design, displayed reality, non-verbal discourse or action. We
should not yield to their efforts to have their creations pass for art, like Fumaroli, who, in a reconciliatory effort, just wants to discern
separate domains of art. It matters equally to recognise that realistic
rendering is certainly a great achievement of Western art, but that,
precisely therefore, deviation of this ideal acquires an expressive
quality in its own right. We have to condemn the rejection of realistic
rendering as well as of deviations from it: thanks to the achievements
of academic and (early) modern art, the artist disposes of a whole array
of ways of rendering according to diverse purposes. And he is allowed to
conjure up existing as well as non-existing worlds, 'abstract' forms
like those in Franz Marc's 'Kämpfende Formen' included.
Harouel's narrow definition undermines above all his own reasoning, as
Kostas Mavrakis
already remarked. If it were true that photography is
not art because it is not transfiguring the real world, or because it is
mechanised, how comes that Turner, Delaroche and their successors felt
so threatened and had to summon up such heavy artillery?
CULPRIT (1) PHOTOGRAPHY
And that brings us to our next point: the role of photography.
Harouel brings his own version of the thesis that the invention
of photography had a decisive influence on the development of painting.
We can criticise the details of his version. Thus, Kostas Mavrakis
reminds of the fact that portrait painters were not at all outcompeted
by the photographers: 'At the beginning of the twentieth century,
John Singer Sargent, Giovanni Boldini, Jacques-Emile Blanche, Sir Philip
Làszlo have an immense success on an international level, and up to the
fifties and sixties, Pietro Annigoni, Karel Willinck
obtain commissions from the highest personalities, crowned heads
included'. And that goes not only of France.
.
A more important objection is that photography cannot have
been the main responsible for the scorned development of painting. Similar developments in music and literature
can be observed, although there are no
equivalents of the invention of photography: think of the development
from Wagner to Schönberg, or of the development that leads to Mallarmé.
And, as again
Kostas Mavrakis remarks, from way back it is possible to make moulds,
whereas sculptors never resorted to them.
Let us also remark that the advent of photography has its roots in the
techniques developed by the old masters themselves - think of the
diverse forms of automatisation of production ( the use of corrosive
substances in etching, Dürer's perspective device, the camera obscura - think of the Hockney-Falco
hypothesis) and of the use of the mirror (da Vinci). Why should these devices only become suspect from 1850 onward?
And - last but not least - Harouel overlooks the fact that deviations
from 'true to nature rendering' were practised long before the advent op
photography: it suffices to refer to painters like Greco, Velazquez, the
late Goya, Turner.
It is remarkable that Harouel regards the influence of
photography only from the point of view of rendering, and not from the
point of view of subject matter. In the beginning, photography took over
the traditional genres of painting, but it soon proceeded to introducing
entirely new 'genres': think of reportage and documentary photography
(war, exploitation, disasters), nature photography, microphotography, street
photography, aerial photography, space photography, travel, erotic
photography and what have you. And that goes also for the more advanced
forms of prints, that are overlooked by Harouel: think of the cartoon
and the comic. Conversely, modern painting entered new imaginary worlds:
abstract art and surrealism.
CULPRIT(2): MILLENARISM/OBSCURANTISM
We can largely follow
Harouel when he denounces the millenarian body of thoughts and the
concomitant obscurantism that has been invoked to justify modern art and
that has been embraced by many a modern artist. Still, we have to make some remarks.
To begin with, it should be reminded that the artists of the Ancien
Régime not seldom served as mouthpieces of often equally questionable
ideologies - suffice it to refer to the reigning feudal ideologies or to
the - equally millenarian - Christendom, or to the influence of
Neo-Platonism on Renaissance art. Harouel is right when he claims that the
concomitant 'afterworlds' are rendered 'true to nature' - from Bosch to
the pre-Raphaelites. But he forgets that this goes also for figurative
painters like Dali and Ernst.
Next, it catches the eye that Harouel does not even mention more secular
descendants of German philosophy like Freud, who nevertheless exerted a
profound influence on modern art. Even less do we hear of art theories
that have been developed in the twentieth century to justify the
development of modern art, and that have nothing to do with German
idealism: suffice it to refer to authors like Roman Jakobson in
Russia, Gombrich,
Nelson Goodman in England,
Arthur Danto in the United States
- but above all to Ferdinand de Saussure, Jean-Paul Sartre, Merleau-Ponty,
Roland Barthes,
Claude Lévi-Strauss, Jean Genette, Jacques Derrida, Deleuze and Guattari, Jean Baudrillard,
Michel Foucault, Louis Althusser, Jean-François Lyotard, Jacques Rancière
en
Alain Badiou.in France. Why target only German idealism and its
predecessors in German mysticism and Gnosis?
Finally, Harouel giver no reply to the question why the
scorned philosophers themselves developed such
theories in the first place. In Harouel's approach, which owes much to Pareto,
they must equally have had their 'deeper reasons'. One of the most
popular explanations is the failure of the revolution in Germany, which
made dream of less profane revolutions. This kind of explanations
applies
also for the failure of the communist revolution in Western Europe, and
of the revolt of Mai 1968.
It is remarkable that Harouel does not resort to a nearly related, very
popular, but inadequate explanation: the decline of religion as the real
breeding ground of art - 'la rupture avec le sacré' (Roger Scruton, Jean Clair),
although it might be implicated in the idea of contemporary art as a
'secularised religion'.
CULPRIT (3): CAPITALISM AND THE FREE WEST
In his fourth chapter, Harouel introduces political regime and classes
(capitalists). But he restricts this approach to the period after the
second World War. And that results in a distorted picture. Let us pull out some more historical registers.
For a long time, art has been supported by clergy and aristocracy. The
ascending bourgeoisie initially emulated these classes, but gradually began to
develop its own progressive identity, which it found readily in modern
art that equally was out at distinguishing itself from the art of the
Ancien Régime and its academies. It is with such progressive bourgeoisie that modern art
found its first devotees, just think of Gertrud Stein, Schtschukin,
Kahnweiler, Behrens,Thyssen-Bornemisza, Barnes...
But, for the same reason, also lots of adherents to the entire spectrum
from anarchism and socialism, and soon also to fascism (Mussolini, Goebbels),
aligned themselves with modern art.
First under Stalin, then under Hitler, the tide turned - among
others because the 'people' took not so much interest in modern art. To be
sure, for a long time, 'the people' remained devoted to the kitschy
cast-offs of the Ancien Régime, but it became increasingly attracted to
another anti-aristocratic and anti-bourgeois form of art: the scorned
culture industry, especially after the Second World War. Harouel is
right when he points to the fact that modern art was not precisely
popular before the Second World War. But he is wrong when he suggests
that the then academic art was universally acclaimed.
The turn in the Soviet Union and Nazi Germany
resulted in a new divide. But it was a rather contradictory one. During
the World Exhibition of 1937
- the year of Hitlers 'Entartete Kunst' - the modernism of the Guernica
as well as the socialistic realism of the Soviets were played off against fascism.
Meanwhile, the US had welcomed many a modern artist that had been
expulsed by the Nazis. It became apparent that the local production was
not only mainly academic, but also socially inspired.
After the victory on Hitler and the beginning of the Cold War, the higher
bourgeoisie in the US begins to oppose academic art, not so much because
it would be feudal, as rather because it could be scorned as fascist and
communist - totalitarian and propagandistic. The repressive state
replaces the Ancien Régime as the enemy of the entrepreneur. Especially abstract expressionism
seemed predestined to be a flag on the new battlefield: its abstraction was
the counterpart of the totalitarian propaganda, and its boundless
creativity that of the straightjacket of academism. At the same time,
it distinguished the higher classes from the populace that grew mad of
the soaring culture industry - the popular reaction against the
terror of Hitler and Stalin.
In Europe, things were different. Here, it is not so much the political
and economical heroes of the Free World who set the tune, but rather the
intellectuals. In their view, the defeat of Hitler was rather a step
toward the impending advent of communism. But their enthusiasm was increasingly dampened
by the development of the communist regimes in the Soviet Union and
China. Already before the war, they had forsworn socialist realism, so
that they continued to associate modern art with real socialism, and not
with American capitalism, especially since the latter seemed to be
epitomised in the soaring culture industry of the masses. The
spokesmen of this approach are the Frankfurter Schule, but increasingly
also the above mentioned French philosophers. A whole array of anti-stalinistich but
anti-capitalistic philosophies unfolds. The failure of the revolt of Mai
1968 leads to a radicalisation of modernism. Meanwhile, the new
generation of the baby-boomers vents its unease in the scorned culture industry, which is
experienced not so much as a degradation of high art, as rather as the
voice of the oppressed, first the blacks, but soon generalised to a
universal protest in rock 'n roll. Let us remark that the association of
modern art
with socialism does not mean that the artists themselves were leftists:
in reality, they were mostly adepts of the countless obscurantist
philosophies scorned but Harouel, and they reveal themselves increasingly
as unabashed entrepreneurs, who are no longer prepared to hide
themselves behind a 'critical' imago (see Wim Delvoye).
Things become different with the advent of Thatcher and Reagan, and the fall of the Iron Curtain. Marxism and related ideologies are denounced
as 'big stories'. People turn their backs on ideologies as such, and
come to adhere an individualistic postmodernism, that nevertheless seems
perfectly adapted to the 'big practice' of neoliberalism. Modernism, that
radicalised under the auguries of Marxism, becomes the playground of
ambitious ego's that feel hampered by institutions and conventions of
all kinds. And that is what they have in common with the new
entrepreneurs: capitalists like Charles Saatchi with his
Young British Artists in
England, and François Pinault and
Bernard Arnault with their 'Art contemporain' in France. What in the
beginning was a battle against the Ancien Régime, and was gradually transformed
into a battle against totalitarianism, ends up as a struggle against
regulation and 'collectivism' as such.
Let us examine against this background the version of Harouel.
There is no denying that capitalist regimes through the CIA as well as
communist regimes through the VOKS (the All-Union Society for Cultural
Relations with Foreign Countries) have tried to extend the Cold War to
the cultural front. As opposed to the Soviet Union, that bestowed the
Stalin Peace Prize to Picasso (or the Stasi that supported
Günter Walraff), the CIA stroke the right chord. But it thereby
only
supported a movement that was more inspired by Marxism. The
intervention of the CIA may only have contributed to the take over of the
art scene by New York. And that only paved the way for the increasing
influence of the new entrepreneurs. The whole story of the CIA is no
more than a rather blown up conspiracy theory, which nevertheless does
not explain why the success of 'l'art contemporain' only started
when the CIA left the scene.
Let us remark, finally, that in Harouels analysis in terms of classes
and political ideologies, the nations are missing. That catches the eye,
because Harouel culprits have an outspoken national identity: the
Germans with their idealism and the Americans with their ideology of the
free world. It catches the eye especially since, up to the take over of
New York, France happened to be the locus delicti of the
avant-garde, and after the take-over, the locus delicti of the
intellectual 'obscurantism' in matters of art. The title of Serge Guilbaut's
book, to which Harouel repeatedly refers, sounds: 'How New York stole the notion of modernism from Paris' (1985).
One cannot escape the impression that the reaction against 'l'art
contemporain', which is more heavy in France than in any other country,
is fuelled by the fact that the US set the tune in matters of
contemporary art, and no longer Paris. Daniel Buren in the Palais-Royal
was not easy to stomach for many a Frenchman, but Jeff Koons in Versailles was
really a bridge too far.
Generally speaking, it must be said that sociological considerations
like those above may well be interesting, but are in no ways relevant to
the status of the art works. From a sociological and political view - as
well as from the perspective of modern art - Richard Strauss' 'Vier letzte Lieder'
are no less than the scandal of scandals. But from a musical point of
view, they belong to the treasures of classical music.
CULPRIT (4): THE NEW RICH AND THEIR LACK OF CULTURE
In that same chapter, Harouel denounces the 'uncultivated', who may be
good entrepreneurs, but are so busy as to find time to remedy
their lack of culture - and hence are predestined to resort to 'le non-art'.
Even when the argument may apply in many cases, it also applies to
notorious examples from the Ancient Régime. Let us also remark that it is
seldom the entrepreneurs themselves who devote themselves to modern art,
but rather their heirs. And these heirs could lead a life of leisure: Gertrud Stein, Peggy
Guggenheim, Hans Heinrich Thyssen-Bornemisza, Nelson Rockefeller are sons or daughters of. Or we
are dealing with entrepreneurs who could rest on their laurels, like Albert C. Barnes.
It may nevertheless be true that there is an increasing number of rich people who
descry in contemporary art only a logo that matches theirs - think of Nelson Rockefeller,
who called abstract expressionism ''free enterprise
painting'. And that applies not only to entrepreneurs, but also to
politicians: one can justifiably question the cultural background of
many a minister of culture, who is only out at adding the logo of famous
artists to his own.
But Harouel puts the question in the wrong terms. The question is what
we understand as culture. When we describe what Harouel calls 'le non
art' in positive terms as design,
displayed reality and non-verbal statements or actions, then the scorned
'uncultivated' might have their own culture - even when the
question remains whether we are dealing here with high culture. But it is
perhaps better to leave the question of 'high' and 'low' culture out of
consideration here. We could as well approach the question not in terms
of culture, but in terms of art. In a world where non-art can pass for
art, the competence in dealing with art diminishes accordingly. Since
the share of non-art increases steadily, the sensibility required to
deal with art threatens to disappear. All the more since
dealing with art always presupposes specialisation, not only in one of
the arts, but also in specific periods. The odds that devotees of
'contemporary art' are not interested in the art of the past, are all
the more real, since contemporary art is essentially a continued
negation of the art of the past. When such specialists become leading
buyers and policymakers, we have a real problem. Especially since
the Western world will increasingly be referred to the background.
China and its neighbours not only deliver outstanding performers of
Western classical music, but also figures like Ai Weiwei, who may be a dissident, but
is nevertheless part of the national - there are some 300.000 dollar
millionaires in China - and international jet set of Harouel's 'non-art'.
We encounter a similar problem in education - an aspect of the problem
which seems to escape Harouel's attention.
Already form the first World War onwards, the academic curriculum has
been replaced with a training where the divide between fine and applied
arts is lifted, exemplary in the Bauhaus. Especially from the sixties
onwards, the art schools are modernised at an increasing pace. After
drawing, not only the handicrafts are dropped, but even the advanced
technologies, under the motto that art is a question of ideas: after the designification, now also the conceptualisation of
the art schools. Add to
that that for the same reason also the initiation in the 'canon' is
pushed to the background, and we have come full circle. A same reasoning
applies to the education in art history and art philosophy.
L'ART CACHé
The shortcomings of Harouel's analysis become apparent when he comes up
with the painters who are supposed to be relegated to the catacombs by
'le non-art - Aude de Kerros' 'art c'aché:
Edward Hopper, whom he esteems to be the most important painter of the
twentieth century, next to Thomas Hart Benton and Grant Wood (p.143-144).
He rejects Lucian Freud
because of his emphasis on 'the ugliness of things' (p. 132) and
because his lack of 'transfiguration of the real'' (p. 133). Peter Doig is
recognisable as well as pleasing, but resorts to the
mechanical procedures of photography (p. 133). Granted, this is a rather
meagre harvest especially when we compare these painters with their
predecessors - or with the better painters in the modern tradition.
The decay of education can hardly be invoked: it was mainly intact when
Harouels examples were trained. Hopper was educated at the New York Institute of
Art and Design, Grant Wood at the Art Institute of Chicago, Thomas
Hart Benton at the same Art Institute of Chicago and at the Académie
Julian in Paris - not precisely the Ecole des Beaux Arts, but still an
academy where figures like
Bouguereau teached, whom Harouel views favourably. Did the more
talented painters succumb to the temptations of success on the scene of
modern art? How comes that Harouel's cultivated classes - the old
aristocrats and the clergy - were no longer prepared to take their
responsibilities as authoritative buyers or sponsors?
Why did they equally join the new trend? Think of the clergy that opted
for Matisse and his Chapelle du Rosaire in Vence, or for Corbusier and
his Notre Dame du Haut in Ronchamps. Why did the church after Vatican II
reject the venerated Gregorian chant? And compare the stance of figures
like Prince Charles with that of the Belgian queen Paola who supports
figures like Jan Fabre, who was elevated
to the rank of
'Commander in the order of Leopold II', not otherwise than
Paul McCartney by Queen Elisabeth. In any case, the decay of
education can only be invoked to explain the absence of painters trained
after the sixties.
WHERE DID ART GO?
There is more at stake, then, than a derailment of artists under the
auguries of German Idealism and a conspiracy of the Free World - suffice
it to refer to the 'culture industry' which is responsible for the fact
tot modern art as well as academic art have become marginalised.
Harouel does not answer the question why the 'artists without art' could
so easily take over. When the academic art of the twentieth century is
so valuable, how comes that it is not widely acclaimed and that there
are so few gifted artists who endorse it? It may be true
that the creations of the 'artists without art' do not amount to much,
but that goes equally to the paintings of the 'real' artists. Granted:
the works of Hopper are not precisely the pinnacle of the development of
Western painting ...
That is part of the answer to the question how the 'artists without art'
could so unabashedly steal the show. Instead of recognising the problem,
Harouel passes over it as if it did not exist. And that is
perhaps the biggest problem. The theoretical understanding of the
'philosophy' of modern art may leave much to be desired, that applies
even more to the advocates of traditional art. There is no doubt that it
is important to
indicate where the boundaries of art are crossed. But there is no point
in trying to define art in terms of techniques, ways of rendering, stile, let alone the
world view on which it is based, although one may certainly have one's
predilections.
The whole 'querelle de l'art contemporain' only demonstrates how much
both parties seem to be utterly confused.
We need neither a return to better times nor a flight into the future. What
we need is a more enlightened theory of art that avoids the dead ends of
both the theories of 'academic' and
'contemporary' art, a theory that is able to found a new practice of an
art that
is 'contemporary' in the real and full sense of the word
Stefan Beyst,
February 2010.
referrers:
schwarz