INTRODUCTION: MOVEMENT AND MUSIC
Before tackling our actual subject, we have to dispense once and for all with the nearly
ineradicable idea that sound – and by extension music – is the natural
appearance of movement. One becomes easily prey to such
delusion when the non-moving image (sculpture, painting) is contrasted
with music and not with moving visual art (film, video), as happens to
be the case in the context of discussions on ‘the integration of the arts’.
The equation of movement with sound – and by extension with music – may
at least be called peculiar. Leaving apart the movements within the body
(breathing, blood circulation, digestion), every movement is always and
in all its dimensions visible, at least in principle (i.e. when it is
not hidden, which means that it is potentially visible) – think of the
movement of a leopard. Only a minority of movements, on the other hand,
are audible. To begin with, many a movement is not audible at all: think
of birds in the sky and fishes in the water. When audible, it is not
always so: we only hear it when it is nearby. It suffices to refer to
the masterly passage in Nietzsche’s ‘Morgenröthe’ where he describes how
in the midst of the breakers on the rocks you see the sailing ship
silently move over the waves. Conversely, on the sailing ship you hear
the whistling of the wind in the rigging, whereas the breakers seem to
silently rage against the cliffs …When movements are audible, we only
hear fragments of it: of complex movements such as marching or trotting,
we only hear the boots or hooves coming down. It appears that movement
and sound are not really compatible. That has from way back been a
problem in music: how to make music out of the movement of waves or
falling leaves, flying birds (Schubert’s ‘Die Krähe’) or swimming fish
(‘Schubert’s ‘Die Forelle’), nightfall or sunset – let alone the
‘movements of the soul’, music’s natural domain?
This is not the place to examine why music has nonetheless been the
natural habitat of (foremost expressive) movement. Let us only remind of
the fact that the sounds of music are experienced as an incitement to
move, which not only propels ourselves, but in the first place the imaginary beings thus conjured up. Music not only commands facial
expressions, gestures and postures, but immobility as well – think of
Mahler’s Mitternachtslied. Music not only conjures up the objective,
optic appearance of a moving being, but in the first instance its
subjective intention to move. That is why it always also renders the
‘sentence structure’ of the movement. More than any other art, music is
able to articulate the unfolding of movement: with infallible certainty
it not only indicates its beginning and end, but also every pause
underway, every hesitation or every determination in its unfolding. All
this cannot be deduced with equal certainty from the visual appearance
of movements (see also: Mimesis and music).
MOVEMENT AND VISUAL ART
Of all the senses, the most appropriate to the perception of moving objects is
the eye. Yet, paradoxically enough, whereas the mimetic technology has
no difficulties in conjuring up the most diverse movements through
sounds, it is far more difficult to render movement visually.
The most obvious solution is to restrict oneself to human movement, which
can easily be rendered by actors or dancers. Far more
difficult is conjuring up the movement of non-human beings and objects.
For a long time, there has been no other possibility than resorting to
the human body. Humans may be hidden in the objects that have to be
brought to life: think of the Chinese dragons, the African masks, and
the European giants. In the ‘Bauhaus’, abstract forms were brought to
life through human supports (Schlemmers’ triadic ballet). Or human
movement may be transferred to objects indirectly: the strings or the
hand in the puppet theatre, Kandinsky’s abstract theatre, Depero’s ‘Progetto
di scena mobile’. Or one might, finally, resort to machines:
mechanically moved statues and automata: think Fellini’s Casanova
dancing with an automaton, singing and fluttering birds, clocks with
moving figures, evolving landscapes or skies, Depero’s ‘Complessi &
plastica girante’ or ‘Complesso plastico colorato motorumoristica
simultaneo di scomposizione a strati’, Tatlin’s rotating blade,
Tingueley’s moving assemblages, Bury, and so forth. But it is only
computer technology that makes it possible to make all kinds of robots.
Even more difficult is it to conjure up movement through a
two-dimensional image. Up until the eighteenth century – leaving apart
the shadow puppets in Java or the shadows in Plato’s cave – it has only
been possible to make a two-dimensional image move through intervention
of the hand, as with a kaleidoscope. More sophisticated is movement
induced through the mechanics of a keyboard. Inspired through Newton,
the Jesuit Louis-Bertrand Castel built a colour-keyboard in 1725. It
consisted of two coloured discs with twelve colours, corresponding to
the twelve tones of the scale. In 1757, an adept of Castel built a
‘eye-clavichord’ with five hundred candles behind a row of fifty boxes
which opened when a key was struck, while at the same time a tone was
heard. In 1879 Frédric Kastner succeeded in building a ‘pyrophone’: an
organ with glass cylinders filled with gas that produced tones, which
inspired the ‘light -organs’ developed by Brainbridge Bischop in 1888,
Wallace Remington 1895, and a light organ with 4 x 7 coloured electric
bulbs by the Futurists Corra and Geinnate. Ivan Vysjbegradsky designed a
light dome for a ‘Temple of light’. In the thirties, complicated
‘spectaculars’ were developed with electric bulbs and neon light for
advertising purposes. With all these colour- or light organs, the form
is determined by the character of the source of light (the arrangement
of the lamps) or by the screen on which the light is reflected (screen,
wall, dome). There have been increasing efforts to have also the form
change. This was realised in the ‘sonochromatoscope’ of Alexander Laszlo
(coloured forms on turning discs projected on a screen behind a
pianist), the optophonic piano of Baranoff-Rossiné built in the
Wchutemas in Moscow in 1923 (a piano with coloured discs moved through
keys), the ‘MobilColor Projectors’ of Dockum, the ‘Lumia’ of Wilfred,
the ‘Lumigraph of Fishinger. Only the development of film offered
limitless prospects. To begin with, also real movement could be rendered
in moving images. Every constraint is lifted through special effects.
Any imaginable being can be brought to life through animation. Animation
may also be used to bring abstract forms to life, which is often called
‘visual music’ or ‘absolute film’: think of artists such as the
Futurists Carra and Ginna, of Bauhaus people like Vic Eggeling, Walter
Ruttmann, Oskar Fischiner, Hans Stoltenberg, Hans Richter and of Survage
in France. In the sixties, a new generations falls in: John & Jams
Whitney, Jordan Belson and Harry Smith. But above all the computer
offers limitless possibilities, even when they often seem to be
inversely proportional to the quality delivered.
Also more primitive efforts must be mentioned: think of Esher or some
forms of Op-art and holograms.
All these forms of moving plastic art are often combined with sound or
music. This can be realised through a separate production of sounds
(such as thunder in the theatre) or through music accompanying a silent
film. Soon, the sound-track is developed: the sound of movement and
dialogue is added to the image. With moving abstract forms, it is mostly
music that must fill he gap.
MOVEMENT IN NON-MOVING OBJECTS: DYNAMICS
But there is more. Movement can be understood as a the mere change of
position (of the whole or parts) in space. But there is also something
like ‘force’, ‘dynamics’, ‘will’ (intention). This kind of movement is
to be found foremost in non-moving objects.
To begin with, non-moving objects cannot be grasped in one glance. The
eye only sees the point on which it focuses. It has to scan its object –
a face, a body. In doing so it focuses on points that attract the
attention – the eyes, the lips – and hence follows a hopping trajectory
over the object. The eye also wants to see the ‘lines’ that isolate
figures from their background, and parts of the body from the background
of the body as a whole. The eye cannot catch these lines in one glance
either: it has to follow their course. The same goes for gradients
(especially from black to white) that indicate ‘roundness’. Such ‘movement of perception’ induces us to perceive
contours and surfaces as if they were moving. This is a first source of
a ‘dynamic’ lecture of non-moving objects.
Objects are also susceptible to gravity. They may submit to it and come
to rest on the earth's surface. But they also can struggle against it:
as when plants grow towards the light of the sun, when trees pave their
way to the light, when animals erect themselves on their legs. But it is
above all man who, standing on his two legs, has to permanently hold his
head and trunk in balance (Schopenhauer: marching as an postponed
falling). A body may proudly erect itself against gravity, or
desperately let itself hang. Through ‘anthropomorphising’ extension also
lifeless matter may be experienced as being in rest (a boulder or a flat
polder) or struggling against gravity (a rock, a volcano or a mountain).
The same play of forces is at work in architecture: the horizontal
architrave resting in all its breadth upon rising columns. A triangle is
grounded with its base on the earth's surface while its two rising sides
are striving upwards. Foremost with geometrical forms the movement of
perception comes to endorse the movement of dynamics: the curves of a
hill are read from the left to the right, and the sides of the triangle
of a pyramid or a roof as an upward movement.
With living beings, already the structure of their bodies betrays the
direction in which they will move: eyes and mouth are situated on a
‘front’. The mere orientation of their face indicates in which direction
they are about to move, or to which object they are relating. Also the
posture of their limbs betrays which movements they intend to perform:
the paw is already slightly lifted up or the head recoils anxiously.
Above all in man there are countless ‘intentional movements’ from which
we can read movements forthcoming or just finished (see Freud's analysis
of Moses). In that sense every body, even when it completely stands
still, is one potential movement, of bundle of forces about to burst out
in an action.
To distinguish it from real movement, we should rather call this kind of
movement ‘dynamics’. The term ‘visual music’ would only be misleading.
THE RENDERING OF MOVEMENT IN NON-MOVING VISUAL ART
Immobile objects may be further dynamically charged when conjured up
through a non-moving image.
The two-dimensional non-moving image is a whole that has to be scanned
step by step by the eye. Therein, looking at an image resembles the
reading of a text. The plane is read according to a standard itinerary:
from the left to the right, from below to above and diagonally from left
under to right above. This itinerary is further determined through the
geometrical build-up of the plane. From way back, artists have been
using this phenomenon to confer an extra dynamic to their paintings. It
suffices to place one of the above mentioned movements (the movement of
perception, the opposition against gravity, intention) on one of the
above mentioned axes, to lend them additional dynamics. The effect may
even be heightened by moving against the dynamics of the plane, as in
Michelangelo’s God creating Adam. The reverse is also true: standstill
or inwardness can be made more static by balancing dynamics on all the
axes (static composition).
But the non-moving image can also render actually moving bodies:
running, falling, flying and dancing beings or acting humans. Most
suited is the culmination point of a given movement, when it ‘stands
still’ for one moment, often as a transient pose with an expressive
freight of its own: think of the moment when the receding arm reverses
its movement to proceed to throwing (discobolos), of hips wiggling when
dancing of stepping (Botticelli’s or Raphael’s three Graces), of the arm
stretched out to summon up to combat (Delacroix).
TRACES AS VISUAL KINETIC IMPULSES
Already in the real world, movement can also be descried in its traces.
Whoever
sees the traces of the movement of a snake in the sand cannot help from
reading the snake’s movements in it. This holds above all of human
activity: we see the stroke of the knife in the notch. We see the
writing of the hand in the loops of the handwriting – which is the basis
of graphology. We see the laying of the bricks in their succession in a
row. And we see the succession of columns in a gallery as if they have
been put down as a whole. In the diagram of an earthquake below, the eye
reads the movements of the needle:
|
In that sense, traces are transformed into kinetic impulses:
impulses that
provoke movement. They stir the irresistible need to repeat or
recreate the movement to which they owe their existence. This is only
strengthened through the scanning lecture of a row of columns, or a layer
of bricks.
TRACES OF THE MAKING OF THE IMAGE
This goes above all for the traces left by the making of the image. To
be sure, not every creative process leaves its marks in the end product.
A painted surface or the contours of a figure may totally dissolve into
the image. But, even then do we read the natural gradients or lines as
traces of the activity of the artist. We have seen how the contours and the undulations of the
surface are being scanned by the eye. That they are now created by an
artist really transforms their course into a movement. The artist may so
design the surface or the contours that the movement becomes a real
‘flow’ animating the body – think again of the ‘movement’ in the arm of
God creating Adam in the Sixtine Chapel. The effect is further enhanced
when the stream coincides with a genuine movement, such as Venus’ mane
undulating in the wind with Botticelli, or when the movement of a stride
is endorsed by the flow streaming towards the point of the foot, as in
Botticelli’s marvellous ‘Flora’ in the Primavera. There, the threefold
descending flow (of making, of perception and of real movement) is
further enhanced through Flora’s self-confident erect posture, opposing
gravity. And, finally, the dynamics of the whole are further heightened
through the downward dynamics of the line of the geometric grid that
divides the rectangle in three parts: both foot and compositional line
point to two thirds of the base of the rectangle.
Thus is unfolded a synergy of forces bringing the immobile image to
life. In this light, one can only look down pityingly on the countless
efforts of the Futurists to render movement through piling up its
multiple phases in one and the same image: think of Bragaglia’s
photographs with multiple exposure, Balla, not to mention Russolo’s
simply ridiculous ‘Music’.
The diverse phases are not read as a continuous movement but as a
rhythmically articulated one.
INCREASING AUTONOMY OF DYNAMICS IN VISUAL REPRESENTATION
In the beginning, the artists tried to get rid of traces altogether, or,
the put it more accurately: they let them match the even surface or
disappear in the unbroken flow of the contour (da Vinci's 'sfumato').
This is not always possible: think of drawings, but foremost of copper
engravings or etchings, where surfaces cannot but be rendered through
lines. In handling such unruly media, the artist soon learned that
additional expressive powers could be obtained through bringing the
traces in the forefront. They now could be read as traces of the
movement of the hand that produced them. In a first phase, the artist
might accentuate the contours, already made fluent through idealising
the model, through a line, however ‘invisible’ it may be (see again:
Botticelli). An even stronger effect may be obtained when lines or
strokes are deliberately placed in the forefront. This may be achieved
through a synthetic summary of the separate lines of the real contour,
such as the single line with which Matisse circumscribed his figures.
More often, the contour or surface is divided in separate
lines or strokes. Also here the traces of the making join the movements
of their lecture and the many further forces at the disposal of the
artist (Klee). A remarkable feat is the way in which
Judith Schils
succeeds in rendering the music emanating from the piano - or the
psychic energy projected in it - in her series 'Pianos':
|
From the nature of the traces the character of their maker may be
deduced: from the patient and poised movements on Dürer’s copper
engravings to the transport in Van Gogh’s strokes.
|
The dynamics of the cuts or strokes endorses the overall expression of
the representation.
AUTONOMY OF THE DYNAMICS OF CREATION
The increasing autonomy of the dynamics of creation
comes to split the image in two parts: on the one hand it shows a visual
representation, on the other hand it evokes the activity of its maker
through the expressive traces of the creative process.
The rift may be restored in two ways. Either the artist continues to
subordinate the traces to representation, or he cancels representation
altogether and restricts himself to expression through traces as such.
This latter solutions results in a kind of self-portraiture through the
artist (Matiushin, Pollock).
|
Undoubtedly, through such resigning the visual arts come to resemble
music. Lines and strokes are visual traces, the counterparts of the
tones produced on an instrument as audible traces of the activity of the
player. And they equally partake of measure and rhythm: the lines of
strokes may be of the same length and be located at equal distances, or
they may vary in length and direction while being located at varying
distances. The differences in ‘weight’, which in music are often
indicated through loudness, may here be evoked through variations in the
amplitude of the curves or through the ‘weight’ of the descending
movement.
It seems that we here can – this time justifiably – speak of ‘visual
music’. But there remains a crucial difference. Music does not evoke the
activity to which it owes its existence: it is only a means of evoking
the movements of an imagined being. In Schubert’s ‘Die Krähe’, the
fingers of the pianist do not conjure up the movement of his fingers,
but the movement of the wings of the crow that accompanies the walker to
his grave. The dynamics of visual traces, on the other hand, are a
rather primitive form of music: a form of music in which the sounds only
evoke the movement to which they owe their existence. Even when the
title ‘visual music’ might justifiably be conferred to visual traces,
this is done so somewhat prematurely. We only have to deal with a
preliminary stage of music. Van Gogh’s strokes are a portrait in the
same way as the sound of marching boots are a portrait of soldiers
marching.
DECORATIVE ART AS NON-MOVING VISUAL MUSIC
As soon as visual art resigns from the task of conjuring up a visual
representation, it unawares comes to resemble the decoration on pottery,
furniture, textile and architecture.
Strange enough, it is precisely in this domain – from way back excluded
from the domain of art – that traces are distancing themselves from the
activity to which they owe their existence. Take a motif such as
meanders. No doubt, a meander is born out of a movement as simple as
moving up and down a stylus in the clay. But the decorative purpose
imposes a logic that is alien to the original operation: the movement
has to be continued along the entire circumference of the pot, and its
end must so join its beginning, that the meander seems to continue
endlessly. Since this cannot be achieved in one single movement of the
hand, the continuity of the end result is no longer a trace of a real
movement. This is a first step in the emancipation of visual music: the
movement that is conjured up is no longer the movement of the hand. Herein it
comes to resemble the movements that are conjured up in music, which have equally
nothing to do with the movement of the pianist’s fingers.
Precisely the logic of decoration engenders an increasing divergence
between the movement of making and the movement conjured up
through its traces. The emancipation does not stop here. A second
meander may be so superposed over the first one that it comes to mirror
the first one. In the result, it is not visible that the motif has
been made through separate movements of the hand in two phases: both
movements are read simultaneously as an uninterrupted and endless flow.
The trace is still read as the trace of an activity, but it is no longer
the activity to which it owes its existence. This is from the beginning
so with wholes that come about through addition of operations on
different levels. In a brick wall, there is the level of the succession
of the bricks within the row and - on a higher level - the succession of
rows piled up one upon the other. The movement of making is dissociated
from the movement of reading: it no longer matters whether a gallery
came about through piling up the drums of one column after another or
whether first all the first drums were laid, and then the second ones,
until all the columns could be crowned with a capital. We can read both
movements separately at random.
In this respect decorative art is elevated to the level of music. Only
here can we speak of a ‘visual music’ in the real sense of the word:
both conjure up movements that differ from those of whom they are the
traces. Even when the difference is not so big as between the moving
fingers and the wings of the crow in music.
INTERNAL CONSTRAINTS ON VISUAL MUSIC
In the decorative arts, the development of a genuine visual music is
hampered by an internal limiting factor. Let us first have a closer look
at the traces of making in images that conjure up visual
representations. We only read separate movements in one breath:
where the line or the stroke ends, also the evocation of the movement
stops. We can proceed to the reading of another moving element, but it
is not determined which trace should be read next: when reading Van
Gogh’s strokes I can begin wherever I like, and continue wherever I like.
This goes especially when the artist resigns from conjuring up a
representation. The traces of his activity are piled up into a kind of
‘clouds’: clouds of angles with Picasso’s cubist works, clouds of
plusses and minuses with Mondrian, clouds of dots with Agosto Giocametti
or Matiusjin, clouds of ‘lasso-movements’ with Pollock.
The absence of a linear reading can be remedied through so linking up
the separate elements that a compelling sequence of reading is imposed.
The separate elements may be placed on a horizontal row, as the
decorative arts do from way back. The separate movements are then
absorbed in an endless flow as in a garland or a string of beads and all
kinds of friezes.
The most obvious way of having such succession continue endlessly, is to
curb it around the surface of a cylinder, such as the surface of an
amphora or a string of beads.
On a flat surface, though, the élan of the movement inevitably comes to
stop at the edges. A primitive means of letting the movement
continue nonetheless, is to prolong the surface. This solution is chosen
by many a painter who wanted to produce ‘visual music’, without having
properly understood the problem (Vking Eggeling Horizontal-vertikal-Orchester
I 1919/1929; Richter: ‘Fuge’ 23 (1923/76) and ‘Orchestration der Fläche’
(1923).
Far more appropriate is to so curb the direction of the succession that
it can be continued within the plane. There are many methods. In a first
series of solutions the movements are arranged around a centre.
Another method consists of piling up increasingly bigger shapes around
one and the same centre (Klee: ‘Polyphon definiertes Weiss; Albers).
Or one might proceed to using different levels, as with writing letters
on a paper, or with brick walls consisting of rows of bricks. In the
latter case, the linear succession is interrupted through an
articulation in ‘rows’ or ‘lines’. The repetition of elements within the
rows is mirrored in the piling up of rows into a surface (Klee’s
chess-board motives).
But also such continuation has its limits: once the surface is covered,
the movement comes to an end. Another method of realising movements on
different levels is to consider parts of the plane as another surface,
wherein a new rhythm is installed. This is the case when a ceiling is
divided into ‘caissons’, each with a rhythm of their own.
Different rhythms may also be combined on one and the same level:
mirroring meanders, combinations of two or more different lines or
series of elements (Klee).
A complex solution consists of producing new surfaces through making
lines cross: the rhythm of the lines engenders a rhythm of shapes (Klee,
Kupka).
Wherever several movements are running together, on the same or on
different levels, one can speak with some reserve of ‘polyphony’ (Klee).
But this is a mere metaphor. Even when there is more than one movement
at the same time, these movements are not at all melodies, and their
reciprocal relation is governed by totally different laws than in
genuine musical polyphony.
All these solutions allow to continue the movement on a higher level.
But they eventually lay bare another weakness of visual music. Again:
when reading such a hierarchic whole, one can begin on whatever level.
It is not determined where the movement begins, and where it has to
continue. Also the tempo can arbitrarily be chosen. That is why visual
music lacks one of the most powerful characteristics of audible music:
the synchronous - communal - reading of movement through all the
listeners.
On top of that, aural music is able to render the course of time as an
organic movement that unfolds from a beginning, through a climax, to an
end. Music achieves this through the use chords. It suffices to listen
to the beginning sentence from the second movement of Beethoven’s
seventh symphony to convince oneself that music is more than a
succession of kinetic impulses. From the very first note onwards, we feel that
this is the beginning of an entire period, how it will unfold and how
long it will go on. The mere rhythm as such itself might be visualised
as follows:
_ . . _ _ _ . . _ _ _ . . _ _ _ . . ___ _ . . _ _ _ . . _ _ _ . . _ _ _ . . ___ |
This is an exact rendering of the duration of time, but what is
evidently lacking is the ‘soul’ of the movement, its 'pulse'. This
wonder is achieved through harmony, which has no visual equivalent. That
is why, in the visual dimension, we can start and stop wherever we like.
In music this is from the beginning excluded.
In non-moving visual music, the effect of harmony can only be hinted at
through the propensity to articulate geometrical figures. A line that
goes up and down has extremities and a centre. Every time the movement
passes through an extreme or a centre, it has performed a ‘period’. Yet
this can not remedy the shortcoming that the beginning as well as the
end must be arbitrarily chosen and that the movement can go on
perpetually. Nowhere is this so evident as in the (round or edged)
spiral: it can go on inwards and outwards, as long as you like.
EXTERNAL CONSTRAINTS ON VISUAL MUSIC
As we have seen, the continuation of a movements on a plane has to
necessarily end up in the development of structures more complex than
the single line that has to be continued. Such complex configuration
threatens to no longer be read as a trace of movement: they rather come
to impose themselves as figurative wholes.
That goes in the first place for the efforts of modern artists that were
out at elevating painting to the level of music. In Pollock’s paintings,
the traces of movement are dissolving into a kind of tangle – and a
tangle is a figure (just like cosmic streams, nebulae and so on).
Nowhere is this so apparent as in Mondrian’s ‘Broadway Boogie-woogie’:
the squares are added up to rows, and these rows in their turn combined
into a chess-board pattern, which is supposed to remind of the map of New
York:
But also pure decorative art is all too readily filled in with
figuration. A curve is naturally transformed into a snake, a centripetal
motif into a flower, and so on. Whence the proliferation of foliage,
grotesques, snakes and dragons, not to mention the vegetal motifs in
Jugendstil:
While dissolving into representation, the dynamics of decorative motifs
is caught in an immobile pattern. Exemplary in fire-work: the explosion
leaves traces that develop into lines, but their momentum is suspended
as soon as we read the whole as a flower.
And so we have come full circle: we are back at the very point where the
trace released itself from the fetters of representation…
Even when it is foremost in the non-representative, ‘abstract’ art that
(non-moving) visual music can flap its wings, it does not really get off
the ground. Its flight is broken in that the dynamic flow has of
necessity to dissolve into a hierarchical organisation of time on
different levels. Furthermore, the trace is all too readily absorbed in
a representation where its dynamics are contained. Aural music easily
gets around such danger precisely because movement as a rule is not
audible, so that the sounds conjuring up movement cannot remind of some
audible appearance. Through such detour, we inadvertently understand why
music has become the natural means of conjuring up movement…
Only when visual music is aware of its constraints can it take a higher
flight. And it can do so only through subordinating itself to, if not
disappearing behind precisely the so scorned representation. Rather
than breaking its élan, representation really emancipates visual music:
it saves the traces from involuntarily dissolving into arbitrary
representation. Precisely through operating within the confines of a
pre-existing representation can traces be read as pure traces – as
visual music – think of Dürer or Van Gogh. And the cleavage within the
image can be mitigated when the visual dynamics are subordinated to the
object represented, as when the traces of the painter’s hand are used in
a self-portrait.
This explains why the dynamics of non-moving representational images is
so much stronger than in the art of mere traces. It suffices to compare
Rubens’ ‘Fall of the Angels’ with some Pollock to convince oneself of
that truth.
And that comparison also teaches another lesson: only through
incorporating visual music can representational art compensate for the
absence of subjective ‘intention’ (‘Wille’) in every visual appearance.
Only thus can the image unfold to a completed visual art, wherein real
movement, movement of perception, struggle against gravity, intentions
and traces of making, join in a meaningful polyphony. A further
advantage is that the organic flow of time, which music is able to
render through harmony, can here be realised through representation. In
this sense painting has always been ‘music’. It is no coincidence that
painters came to admire music precisely when they wanted to shrug off
the yoke of representation, and in so doing precisely broke the backbone
of its genuine ‘polyphonic’ character.
MOVING VISUAL MUSIC
In the moving two-dimensional image (film, video) there are no problems
with rendering a moving object. But the moving visual arts nonetheless
also resort to providing ’visual’ kinetic impulses.
When the body is marching, rowing, dancing, its movements function as kinetic
impulses. The advantage of visual movements is that they contain all the
information that is needed for the imitation of the movement. Audible
impulses
are far more vague: like the baton of the director, they only indicate
the beginning of the movement. Further information about the movement to
be performed has to be conveyed through additional audible signs
(volume, pitch and so on). On the other hand, sound has the advantage
that you do not have to see a movement to be able to imitate it
synchronically.
Just like the drone of the boots can be replaced with the beating on a
drum, also a visual movement can be replaced with a neutral visual
impulse: paradigmatically in the baton of the conductor, which is after
all a purely visual item. But also a electric lamp will do. As soon as
kinetic impulses are thus isolated from the body, movements may be
conjured up that are different from the ones to which they owe their
existence.
There is, hence, also a – this time moving – visual music, that has been
elevated to the level of audible music. Here, all the constraints on the
unfolding of time imposed on non-moving visual music are lifted. No
longer is it necessary to break up time in different hierarchical
levels, nothing opposes a perpetual flow of time. It is also conceivable
that additional information about the kind and character of the movement
could be provided through variations in the source of light. We could
give different colours to bulbs and rays of projected light, or we could
vary their shape, and so on. But precisely the development of a
technology for enhancing the expressive powers of moving visual music
would again engender the temptation to interpret the visual impulses
as representations. Suppose you would try to render the ‘beat’ of a
movement through a succession of circle, square and triangle. You would
be in danger of representing the movement of three separate ‘actors’
rather than as moments of one and the same movement. And, last but not
least, even when moving visual music has a beginning and an end, never will
it be able to let us feel from the very beginning how the flow of time
will unfold. Although there is something that might be called ‘a chord
of colours’, such a chord is merely an isolated, static given. The terms
‘chord’ or ‘harmony’ are rather misleading metaphors. For, in music,
chords are inherently related to other chords: the appearance of one
chord compellingly calls for the appearance of another one. There is no
visual counterpart to the propelling force of chords and their
succession. As opposed to non-moving visual music, moving visual music
even cannot resort to geometrical logic to provide an equivalent for the
overall articulation of time.
Thus the system remains a poor one and it can nearly elevate itself
above the primitive level of dance. The constraints are not merely
technical, they are inherent in the medium itself. Precisely therefore,
moving visual music cannot do without audible music: just imagine a
dance-temple where everybody is moving on the rhythms of a light-show
devoid of music. Music plays the same role for moving visual music as
representation does for non-moving visual music. And that reminds us of
the fact that moving visual music is able to synchronise movement and to
impose its tempo to all viewers, which is impossible in non-moving
visual music.
Movement is not always articulated. Also gradual shifts are conceivable:
think of the change in colours in a sunset, the paradigm of most of the
plastic artists that wanted painting to parallel music. They were out at
freeing colours from the fetters of shape and would have let them change
like the colours in a sunset (Remington). They overlooked that colour is
unconceivable without form: also in a sunset do colours have forms. The
equivalent in music for such gradual shifts are glissandi for pitch,
change in timbre, changes in volume.
CONCLUSION
So, there really is something that may be called ‘visual music’. There
are even two kinds of it: non-moving and moving. But, due to inherent
constraints, they never will develop into full-fledged autonomous
branches of art. Non-moving visual music naturally courts visual
representation or design (pottery, textile, tapestry, architecture) and
moving visual music is doomed to remain a complement to audible music,
if not a mere extension of it.
© Stefan Beyst, November 2001.
referrers:
juan hurlé